Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem

In set theory, the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem, named after Georg Cantor, Felix Bernstein, and Ernst Schröder, states that, if there exist injective functions f : AB and g : BA between the sets A and B, then there exists a bijective function h : AB. In terms of the cardinality of the two sets, this means that if |A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |A|, then |A| = |B|; that is, A and B are equipollent. This is a useful feature in the ordering of cardinal numbers.

The theorem is also known as the Schroeder–Bernstein theorem, the Cantor–Bernstein theorem, or the Cantor–Schroeder–Bernstein theorem.

An important feature of this theorem is that it does not rely on the axiom of choice.

Contents

Proof

This proof is attributed to Julius König.[1]

Assume without loss of generality that A and B are disjoint. For any a in A or b in B we can form a unique two-sided sequence of elements that are alternately in A and B, by repeatedly applying f and g to go right and g^{-1} and f^{-1} to go left (where defined).

 \cdots \rightarrow  f^{-1}(g^{-1}(a)) \rightarrow g^{-1}(a) \rightarrow   a  \rightarrow  f(a) \rightarrow  g(f(a)) \rightarrow \cdots

For any particular a, this sequence may terminate to the left or not, at a point where f^{-1} or g^{-1} is not defined.

Call such a sequence (and all its elements) an A-stopper, if it stops at an element of A, or a B-stopper if it stops at an element of B. Otherwise, call it doubly infinite if all the elements are distinct or cyclic if it repeats.

By the fact that f and g are injective functions, each a in A and b in B is in exactly one such sequence to within identity, (as if an element occurs in two sequences, all elements to the left and to the right must be the same in both, by definition).

By the above observation, the sequences form a partition of the whole of the disjoint union of A and B, hence it suffices to produce a bijection between the elements of A and B in each of the sequences separately.

For an A-stopper, the function f is a bijection between its elements in A and its elements in B.

For a B-stopper, the function g is a bijection between its elements in B and its elements in A.

For a doubly infinite sequence or a cyclic sequence, either f or g will do.

In the alternate proof, C_n can be interpreted as the set of n-th elements of A-stoppers (starting from 0).

Indeed, C_0 is the set of elements for which g^{-1} is not defined, which is the set of starting elements of A-stoppers, C_1 is the set of elements for which f^{-1}\circ g^{-1} is defined but g^{-1}\circ f^{-1}\circ g^{-1} is not, i.e. the set of second elements of A-stoppers, and so on.

The bijection h is defined as f on C and g everywhere else, which means f on A-stoppers and g everywhere else, consistently with the proof below.

Visualization

The definition of h can be visualized with the following diagram.

Displayed are parts of the (disjoint) sets A and B together with parts of the mappings f and g. If the set AB, together with the two maps, is interpreted as a directed graph, then this bipartite graph has several connected components.

These can be divided into four types: paths extending infinitely to both directions, finite cycles of even length, infinite paths starting in the set A, and infinite paths starting in the set B (the path passing through the element a in the diagram is infinite in both directions, so the diagram contains one path of every type). In general, it is not possible to decide in a finite number of steps which type of path a given element of A or B belongs to.

The set C defined above contains precisely the elements of A which are part of an infinite path starting in A. The map h is then defined in such a way that for every path it yields a bijection that maps each element of A in the path to an element of B directly before or after it in the path. For the path that is infinite in both directions, and for the finite cycles, we choose to map every element to its predecessor in the path.

Alternate proof

Below follows an alternate proof.

Idea of the proof: Redefine f in certain points to make it surjective. At first, redefine it on the image of g for it to be the inverse function of g. However, this might destroy injectivity, so correct this problem iteratively, by making the amount of points redefined smaller, up to a minimum possible, shifting the problem "to infinity" and therefore out of sight.

More precisely, this means to leave f unchanged initially on C0 := A \ g[B]. However, then every element of f[C0] has two preimages, one under f and one under g –1. Therefore, leave f unchanged on the union of C0 and C1 := g[f[C0]]. However, then every element of f[C1] has two preimages, correct this by leaving f unchanged on the union of C0, C1, and C2 := g[f[C1]] and so on. Leaving f unchanged on the countable union C of C0 and all these Cn+1 = g[f[Cn]] solves the problem, because g[f[C]] is a subset of C and no additional union is necessary.

Proof: Define

C_0=A\setminus g[B],\qquad C_{n%2B1}=g[f[C_n]]\quad \mbox{ for all }n\ge 0,

and

C=\bigcup_{n=0}^\infty C_n.

Then, for every a ∈ A define


h(a)=
\begin{cases}
f(a) & \mbox{if }a\in C, \\
g^{-1}(a) & \mbox{if }a\notin C.
\end{cases}

If a is not in C, then, in particular, a is not in C0. Hence a ∈ g[B] by the definition of C0. Since g is injective, its preimage g –1(a) is therefore well defined.

It remains to check the following properties of the map h : A → B to verify that it is the desired bijection:

Note that the above definition of h is nonconstructive, in the sense that there exists no general method to decide in a finite number of steps, for any given sets A and B and injections f and g, whether an element a of A does not lie in C. For special sets and maps this might, of course, be possible.

Original proof

An earlier proof by Cantor relied, in effect, on the axiom of choice by inferring the result as a corollary of the well-ordering theorem. The argument given above shows that the result can be proved without using the axiom of choice.

Furthermore, there is a simple proof which uses Tarski's fixed point theorem.[2]

History

As it is often the case in mathematics, the name of this theorem does not truly reflect its history. The traditional name "Schröder-Bernstein" is based on two proofs published independently in 1898. Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1895, while Schröder's name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed while the name of the mathematician who first proved it is not connected with the theorem.

In reality, the history was more complicated:

Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous memoir Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor's paper:


        A \subset B \subset C \quad\textrm{and}\quad |A|=|C| \qquad\Rightarrow\qquad |A|=|B|=|C|

Cantor observed this property as early as 1882/83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers and therefore (implicitly) relying on the Axiom of Choice.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ J. König (1906). "Sur la théorie des ensembles". Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des sciences 143: 110–112. http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k30977.image.f110.langEN. 
  2. ^ R. Uhl, "Tarski's Fixed Point Theorem", from MathWorld–a Wolfram Web Resource, created by Eric W. Weisstein. (Example 3)

References

This article incorporates material from the Citizendium article "Schröder-Bernstein_theorem", which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License but not under the GFDL. Peter Schmitt contributed the History section to Citizendium which TakuyaMurata copied into this article.

External links